Formal fallacies
Denying the antecedent
This fallacy would have the following form:
- If P, then Q.
- Not P.
- Therefore, not Q.
Consider the following argument:
- If Kant was a deontologist, then he was a non-consequentialist.
- Kant was not a deontologist.
- Therefore, Kant was a not a non-consequentialist.
This argument has the form of the fallacy, denying the antecedent. We know that this argument is invalid even if we don’t know what “Kant” or “deontologist” or “non-consequentialist” means. (“Kant” was a famous German philosopher from the early 1800s, whereas “deontology” and “non-consequentialist” are terms that come from ethical theory.) It is mark of a formal fallacy that we can identify it even if we don’t really understand the meanings of the sentences in the argument.
Affirming the consequent
This fallacy has the following form:
- If P, then Q.
- Q.
- Therefore, P.
Here’s an argument which uses silly, made-up words from Lewis Carrol’s “Jabberwocky.” See if you can determine whether the argument’s form is valid or invalid:
- If toves are brillig then toves are slithy.
- Toves are slithy
- Therefore, toves are brillig.
This argument has the form of affirming the consequent. We know that the argument is invalid, even though we haven’t got a clue what “toves” are or what “slithy” or “brillig” means. The point is that we can identify formal fallacies without having to know what they mean.